REVIEW: Why Socrates Died by Waterfield
[ Mark Safranski / “zen“]
Why Socrates Died: Dispelling the Myths by Robin Waterfield
2400 years after his trial and execution at the hands of the restored Democracy, Socrates continues to exert a fascination over the Western mind. He is a seminal figure in the development of philosophy and was part of the cognitive revolution in classical Greece that saw a shift from archaic Homeric values to humanistic, rational and proto-scientific values. The death of Socrates, condemned for thought crimes, was the great contradiction of Athenian self-conception of Athens as “the school of Hellas” and his execution remained an indictment leveled by the enemies of democracy ever since. While the importance of Socrates is universally acknowledged, the exact circumstances and motives for his death remain obscure; ironically, a philosopher who so deeply valued “truth” had prosecutors and apologists equally determined to conceal or distort it.
British scholar and translator Robin Waterfield has attempted, as did radical journalist I.F. Stone a generation earlier, to unearth the truth behind the myths about Socrates. Unlike Stone, Waterfield’s investigation, Why Socrates Died , rests on an extensive career translating and writing about the classics, including the major primary and secondary sources used for his book. This provides a firmer base for the inevitable speculation from limited evidence that is frequently required in historical reasoning about antiquity. Waterfield is also far less influenced by contemporary political and cultural conflicts than was Stone, whose turbulent career as an investigative journalist was intertwined with Cold War controversies and his activities on behalf of the intelligence services of the Soviet Union. Waterfield also understands far better the machinery of the Athenian state and the nature of Greek polytheistic religious life, which Stone erroneously believed had become thoroughly secularized by the time of the trial of Socrates.
Waterfield notes that while it is normal that most of the records of historical events during antiquity are fragmentary or have vanished, we two purported records for Socrates’ defense speech at his trial, one of the prosecution and numerous apologia. Socrates trial was obviously no ordinary law case for impiety, being still recalled by Athenians a half-century later. Nor did the disciples of Socrates who most ardently took up his cause, Plato and Xenophon, wish the case to be forgotten but rather endeavored to protect their master’s reputation for all posterity. Waterfield writes:
….Both Plato and Xenophon wanted to give their readers the impression that a high-minded philosopher was convicted by the stupidity of the mob, but this was an attempt to distract attention from the real reasons Socrates was killed.
The real reason posited by Waterfield was that Socrates was the teacher of Alcibiades and Critias and thus bore some responsibility for the grave misfortunes suffered by Athens during the war and the crimes of the Thirty Tyrants afterwards. Moreover, as Waterfield argues, Socrates was not so much the victim of a political show trial in which Socrates deliberately provoked the democratic faction to kill him, as I.F. Stone argued but was a religious sacrifice or scapegoat for the transgressions of his students against democracy so that a fragile Athenian society could heal its wounds.
Much of the book is devoted to the career of the mercurial and highly charismatic Alcibiades, who entered politics young and as a disciple of Socrates. According to Wakefield, A scion of the greatest of Athenian houses, Alcibiades in his person was emblematic of all of the virtues and vices of the old Athenian aristocracy that had once ruled Athens from the grand council of the Aeropagus. Of the rising generation of young and clever men of good breeding who aimed to play a role in the politics of the radical democracy, Alcibiades had the greatest promise. Highly intelligent, wealthy, handsome and with a magnetic charm, Alcibiades had the natural arête and metis to romance the mob and bend it to his will. It was this that Waterfield argues attracted the attention of Socrates, who saw in Alcibiades and other young men of promising talent he took on as students the future of Athens.
Unfortunately, with Alcibiades, his numerous gifts could never be separated from his equally stupendous flaws – sexual libertinism, flamboyant profligacy, megalomaniacal ambition and reckless hubris – that were frequently his undoing. A psychological chameleon and demagogue, Waterfield argues that the Athenians, as much as they repeatedly forgave and embraced Alcibiades and his schemes, ultimately feared him as an aspiring tyrant. This feeling crystallized into blame for Socrates in the public mind when other students of his who lacked the charms of Alcibiades, notably Critias, sought revolution and oligarchy. Critias’ bloodthirsty pro-Spartan regime as well as the elite’s prior attempt at oligarchy are explained but not with the same space and attention to detail devoted to Alcibiades. One point that Waterfield takes further than most is arguing that Critias aspirations for a morally reformed and less populated Athens are very much in line with the teachings of Socrates. That far from an aberration for whom Socrates bears little responsibility, Critias represented the philosopher’s hopes for Athens and the Athenian democrats who had suffered at the hands of the Thirty Tyrants wanted someone held accountable. That someone was Socrates, whose teachings as it were, would imperil democracy again were he left at liberty.
Waterfield’s handling of the trial itself is less satisfying and includes a lengthy foray into fictive speculation of material prejudicial to Socrates that his notable apologists, Plato and Xenophon, have carefully omitted from their elegies to their beloved master and his trial. The parallels between Athenian religious ceremony and the results of Socrates trial – a trial for impiety held in defiance of the general amnesty that had been decreed for actions under previous regimes – are present. The Greeks did not as a rule go in for human sacrifices in the classical era (though it wasn’t quite as unknown as is commonly believed) but the symmetry is present if more metaphorical than perhaps explicitly religious. It is difficult as a modern to game out exactly where matters of state end and religion begin when the religion is pagan and intertwined in the mind of Athenians with the fate of the state. A debate more for classical scholars than the average layman.
What is difficult to dispute is the centrality of Socrates life in the evolution of Western philosophy and the contradiction he presents for admirers of self-government and free speech and thought as the core of a liberal society. Socrates elenchus is radically subversive; his Homeric tenets on rulership were arch-reactionary even by the standards of his day and Socrates devotion to his beliefs could not be dented even when they required the supreme sacrifice.
What would an American Socrates look and sound like today? How would “the herd” react to his immovable defiance of popular ideologies? Judging by the barometer of social media and the lynch mob mentalities and angry censoriousness that prevail in elite quarters of American life, I’d have to say: poorly. I see no evidence that Americans living in the bastion of civil liberty would prove more tolerant of dissent than did the Athenian democrats who put Socrates to death.
Waterfield has written a lively and informative explanation of a philosopher whose execution casts a long shadow even after two thousand years. Recommended.
May 22nd, 2017 at 5:29 am
Sacrifice of the Logos, Hellene version to compare with Hebrew.
May 22nd, 2017 at 2:31 pm
Very Straussian observation, Charles.
.
Paul Johnson concluded his short popular bio of Socrates with the analogies to Christ and ancient Jewish monotheism
May 23rd, 2017 at 1:52 am
Gentlemen,
.
Recently I read James V. Schall’s (a Jesuit) book Docilitas. His book draws parallels between Socrates and Christ and this passage seemed fitting to quote:
.
.
As we know, the Hellenist informed the early Church in the articulation of the Faith, and the Logos. Schall is a recent discovery and highly recommended—Zen, I believe you’d love this book.
May 23rd, 2017 at 2:43 am
Ordered!
.
I take ye at your word, sir. 🙂
.
You are right Scott that early Christianity was born in the part of the empire that was in the Hellenistic world and in the first three centuries and then after Constantine’s conversion, the Roman elite became increasingly Hellenized. Even in Christ’s day Pontius Pilate probably spoke Koine Greek as well or better than he did Latin. This area however is not my wheelhouse and I could stand to learn more about it
May 23rd, 2017 at 2:58 am
Christians in Rome did not use Latin in the Mass until the middle of the 3rd century. Sounds like Latinization.
May 23rd, 2017 at 12:53 pm
That could be. The Roman poor though spoke always colloquial Latin, the equites and patricians learned Greek and spoke that in preference privately and wrote in it. It might be the Church opted for the language of the poor of the time (I’m guessing – I’m a US-Sov diplo history guy by education 🙂 )
May 23rd, 2017 at 2:28 pm
It always seemed to me that John (the Evangelist) very nicely finessed two lines of thought, that of the Hebrew Dabar or word of creation & command, and that of the Greek Logos or word as blueprint, vision, in the opening of his gospel. As I recall, both CK Barrett and CH Dodd see a connection along these lines. I’d add that a reader fresh in to Alexandria from India might well have read also a reference to Vac, the Sanskrit goddess of speech. I believe the Vedas contain phrasing that comes very close to John 1.1, in two separate short passages: “In the beginning was Speech” and “Speech was verily the supreme Brahman”. FWIW the concept of Vac is pretty rich and deep, as indeed are both Dabar and Logos..
.
There’s also an interesting correlation between Logos and Tao.. which CS Lewis remarks on.